Skip to main content

Main menu

  • Home
  • Current Issue
  • Ahead of Print
  • Past Issues
  • Info for
    • Authors
    • Print Subscriptions
  • About
    • About the Journal
    • About the Academy
    • Editorial Board
  • Feedback
  • Alerts
  • AAPL

User menu

  • Alerts

Search

  • Advanced search
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law
  • AAPL
  • Alerts
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law

Advanced Search

  • Home
  • Current Issue
  • Ahead of Print
  • Past Issues
  • Info for
    • Authors
    • Print Subscriptions
  • About
    • About the Journal
    • About the Academy
    • Editorial Board
  • Feedback
  • Alerts
Research ArticleRegular Article

Reconsidering the Relationship Between Criminal Insanity and Delusions

Linda Gröning, Susanna Radovic and Unn K. Haukvik
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online March 2025, 53 (1) 35-44; DOI: https://doi.org/10.29158/JAAPL.240085-24
Linda Gröning
Dr. Gröning is a Professor, Faculty of Law, University of Bergen, Norway and a Senior Researcher, Regional Centre for Research and Education in Forensic Psychiatry and Psychology, Haukeland University Hospital, Bergen, Norway. Dr. Radovic is an Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, Linguistics and Theory of Science and Centre for Ethics, Law and Mental Health, University of Gothenburg, Gothenburg, Sweden. Dr. Haukvik, is a Professor, Department of Mental Health and Addiction, Institute for Clinical Medicine, University of Oslo, Norway and Senior Researcher, Regional Centre for Research and Education in Forensic Psychiatry and Psychology, Oslo University Hospital, Oslo, Norway.
SJD
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
Susanna Radovic
Dr. Gröning is a Professor, Faculty of Law, University of Bergen, Norway and a Senior Researcher, Regional Centre for Research and Education in Forensic Psychiatry and Psychology, Haukeland University Hospital, Bergen, Norway. Dr. Radovic is an Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, Linguistics and Theory of Science and Centre for Ethics, Law and Mental Health, University of Gothenburg, Gothenburg, Sweden. Dr. Haukvik, is a Professor, Department of Mental Health and Addiction, Institute for Clinical Medicine, University of Oslo, Norway and Senior Researcher, Regional Centre for Research and Education in Forensic Psychiatry and Psychology, Oslo University Hospital, Oslo, Norway.
PhD
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
Unn K. Haukvik
Dr. Gröning is a Professor, Faculty of Law, University of Bergen, Norway and a Senior Researcher, Regional Centre for Research and Education in Forensic Psychiatry and Psychology, Haukeland University Hospital, Bergen, Norway. Dr. Radovic is an Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, Linguistics and Theory of Science and Centre for Ethics, Law and Mental Health, University of Gothenburg, Gothenburg, Sweden. Dr. Haukvik, is a Professor, Department of Mental Health and Addiction, Institute for Clinical Medicine, University of Oslo, Norway and Senior Researcher, Regional Centre for Research and Education in Forensic Psychiatry and Psychology, Oslo University Hospital, Oslo, Norway.
PhD
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • Article
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF
Loading

Abstract

This article discusses the relevance of delusions for a finding of criminal insanity. The authors start from the recognition that the psychiatric notion of delusion is considered relevant to criminal insanity in most jurisdictions and therefore integrates psychiatric perspectives to define delusions. The key focus is on the differences regarding how and why delusions matter legally between the Anglo-American and the Norwegian approach to criminal insanity. The authors argue that Norwegian law provides a new point of entrance to clarify legal implications of delusions but also uncovers further challenges and targets for future research regarding how the law relies upon psychiatric constructs.

  • criminal law
  • criminal responsibility
  • delusions
  • insanity defense

This article examines the role of delusions for criminal insanity between the Norwegian and the Anglo-American systems. The legal doctrine of criminal insanity identifies defendants who cannot reasonably be understood as accountable for their actions. This doctrine provides an excuse from criminal responsibility in most countries.1 Because of the influence of forensic psychiatry in legal practice, criminal insanity is today associated with psychiatric notions of severe mental disorders and especially with psychosis.2,3 Previous studies indicate that a significant number of those acquitted by reason of insanity are diagnosed with schizophrenia.4,5 Moreover, research shows that positive psychosis symptoms and especially delusions are viewed as proof of criminal insanity.6,–,8

Current diagnostic manuals9,10 suggest that a delusion is a belief that is not amenable to change in view of conflicting evidence. Why and how delusions are legally relevant and how these phenomena can be described is, however, open to debate.11 Although Anglo-American jurisdictions apply various legal standards for criminal insanity (e.g., the M’Naughten rules, the American Model Penal Code, the Criminal Code of Canada), they reflect a common “Anglo-American paradigm,” which has framed the international discourse on criminal insanity.12 There are differences between the standards, such as whether they use “know” or “appreciate” in relation to the act, whether that knowledge or appreciation of the wrongfulness of the act (cognitive prong) should denote legal or moral wrongfulness (or both), and whether they include or do not include a volitional prong.1 (Even though the specific term denoting knowledge in the cognitive prong varies across jurisdictions within the Anglo-American paradigm, we will use “understanding” in the following text unless directly quoting use of an alternate term.) Across different legal standards, however, delusions matter as proof of impairments in the defendant’s cognitive or control capacities relevant to the commission of the crime,1,2 so that a causal link between the defendant’s mental state and the crime must be proven. The relevance of delusions for the criminal insanity question thus partly hinges on their content, i.e., what one delusionally believes and how well this explains the crime.

In contrast to the Anglo-American paradigm, Norwegian criminal insanity law does not involve any requirement of a causal link between a defendant’s mental state at the time of the crime and the crime itself. As we will explain further below, what matters is that a (legally specified) state of serious mental disorder was present at the time of the act, where serious psychotic states are of central relevance. Following the rationale of Norwegian law, delusions are relevant as proof that the defendant was in such a state, regardless of how this state influenced the commission of the crime. Thus, the content of delusions is not necessarily the key concern here but rather how delusions indicate a legally relevant and sufficiently serious state of mental disorder.

We use the Norwegian approach as a point of entrance for discussing the legal relevance of delusions for criminal insanity. More specifically, we draw attention to the key difference between the Norwegian approach and the Anglo-American paradigmatic approach. We argue that, although the Norwegian model evades some problems that the Anglo-American criminal justice systems face, it uncovers further challenges in how the law relies upon psychiatric constructs.

First, we provide some initial remarks on the doctrine of criminal insanity and the psychiatric construct of delusions. We then outline the Anglo-American discourse on the legal relevance of delusions and point out some problems with this approach. Next, we describe the alternative Norwegian approach and some challenges this construction faces. Finally, we discuss remaining challenges that are not yet sufficiently clarified given either approach. A central question is how we can understand delusions as proof of legally relevant and sufficiently severe impairments of mental functioning.

Criminal Insanity and Delusions

The criminal insanity doctrine demarcates lack of criminal responsibility and inapplicability of punishment. It is commonly considered to identify those who cannot reasonably be blamed and should be excused for their otherwise criminal actions because, at the time of the act, they were not deemed capable of practical rationality.13,–,16 More specifically, criminal insanity is commonly understood in terms of impairments in the capacities of recognizing and responding to reasons for actions provided by legal (and moral) norms.14,17,18 This doctrine mirrors the criminal law’s premise that a responsible person is able to understand and respect the law and act accordingly.19,20

As mentioned above, current insanity doctrines commonly require that the defendant is experiencing a serious mental disorder at the time of the act, but the criteria for the legal relevance of mental disorders differ between countries.1 At the same time, it is commonly recognized that having a diagnosis, or a symptom, of a severe mental disorder is neither sufficient nor necessary for criminal insanity. What principally matters to criminal insanity is certain functional impairments that are considered to negate capacities needed for criminal accountability.19 Because psychiatric notions of delusions are legally related to such impairments, we need to address these notions before we proceed to the legal questions.

To describe the psychiatric notions of delusions is, however, not straightforward. Despite the descriptions of delusions given in diagnostic manuals of mental disorders, there is currently not a unified definition of this phenomenon within the psychiatric discourse.21 To some extent, different diagnostic manuals are also applying different criteria to account for delusional disorder.22 In addition, there are different approaches to the understanding of mental disorders, from biological to phenomenological perspectives, as well as to the classification of mental disorders.23,24

Within clinical psychiatry, the writings of the psychiatrists Kraepelin and Bleuler from the late 19th and early 20th centuries have been of central importance to the classification of mental disorders, such as schizophrenia (a term coined by Bleuler, first described as dementia praecox by Kraepelin). They did not directly define delusions but described them in their classifications. For example, they described typical delusional symptoms in persons with schizophrenia as believing that they were spied upon, that the atmosphere was poisoned (Kraepelin), or that their brain was being sawn to pieces (Bleuler).25 Later, the influential philosopher and psychiatrist Karl A. Jaspers proposed three criteria to define delusions: false (or impossible) ideas that are uncorrectable and held with extraordinary certainty.26,27 Today, the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Fifth Edition (DSM-5) defines delusions in a similar way as “fixed beliefs that are not amenable to change in light of conflicting evidence” (Ref. 10, p 87), a definition that has generated broad discussions and been criticized for being too narrow.28 Still, it emphasizes an important aspect for our further discussion; that delusions involve, at least to some degree, an inability to form alternative beliefs. This inability, in turn, may constitute the link to the legal notion of criminal insanity in so far as it may hamper the ability to recognize and respond to legal norms.

It is important to recognize the distinction between the content and form of the delusions.25 The delusional content can be of persecutory, referential (e.g., one is not controlling one’s own actions), somatic, religious, or grandiose character. The content of the delusions is understood to be dependent on the experiences and context of the person, and delusions may therefore sometimes be difficult to distinguish from strongly held ideas.29,30 Delusions can also be bizarre, incomprehensible, or nonsensical, i.e., the content is clearly implausible.27,31

The form of a delusion, on the other hand, denotes its structural components. In this context, the origin of the delusion has been considered of great importance. There are different accounts on this matter.28 According to early writings by Schneider and later Jasper, delusions may arise from a real perception followed by a delusional interpretation of that perception, from a delusional interpretation of a real memory, or from the patient’s mood (Wahnstimmung), or they may be autochthonous (i.e., they arise spontaneously).32,33 Other perspectives held today are that delusions arise from a reasoning bias, i.e., the person bases decisions on insufficient information,34 or by a reduced ability to understand other people’s mental states and intentions.35 From a mechanistic point of view, delusions have been suggested to be caused by errors in the interplay between prior beliefs and “correction” signals.36 According to this view, the brain generates internal models of the world that are continuously being updated based on sensory information that confirms or contradicts them. Disrupted ability to adjust these predictions to the incoming sensory information may lead to the formation of delusional beliefs.37,38 Taken together, these different views suggest that the formation and persistence of delusions may be correlated with functional impairments in different cognitive domains independent of the specific content of the delusion. Moreover, disregarding the distinction between content and form, delusions may be related to the presence of other psychopathologies, such as hallucinations, self-disturbances, anxiety, depression, or mania.39 The profile of concurrent symptoms may also affect the form, content, and severity of the delusions.

Finally, it is important to note that delusions can vary in intensity over time.40 That is, they may be held with stronger conviction and affect behavior in some periods but be less pronounced and debilitating in other periods. Thus, the functional impairments associated with delusions and their effect upon persons show great heterogeneity, not only between different individuals but also over time for each individual experiencing delusions.

The Anglo-American Approach

Within the Anglo-American paradigm, rules and doctrines of criminal insanity are built on a mixed model that attributes a weak relevance to mental disorder as an excusing condition.2 This means that, in addition to the presence of a specified condition of mental disorder, it is required that this condition resulted in certain functional impairments that influenced the commission of the crime. In current criminal insanity doctrines, the latter typically concerns the lack of ability to understand and, sometimes, to control one’s actions.1 Although there are different legal accounts of the relevance of delusions in different jurisdictions, they all entail the requirement that the delusion produced, or exemplified, functional impairments relevant to the commission of the crime. Within Anglo-American law, delusions are thus considered as proof of a link between the defendant’s disorder and the committed crime(s). It is not sufficient to have delusions; the defendant’s delusional state must reach a certain level of severity according to legal standards for criminal insanity. Still, this construction with a causality requirement has led to a focus on how the defendant’s delusional beliefs formed motives for actions, i.e., the content of the delusions comes to the forefront.7,11,41,42

When and why someone who is acting from delusional motives should be understood as criminally insane is, however, debated. The controversies regarding the specific relevance of delusions have revolved around legal criteria regarding the defendant’s understanding of the nature and quality of the act and of the defendant’s understanding of the wrongfulness of the act. These criteria are found in many jurisdictions, such as in England and Wales, Scotland, South Australia, New Zealand, many states in the United States, and Canada, although with somewhat different formulations and interpretations with implications for the legal relevance of delusions.1

According to Scottish law, to give an example, delusions may be relevant to the defendant’s understanding of the act. What matters is the defendant’s understanding of the quality of the act, which is understood to include situations where the defendant’s delusional beliefs were providing reasons for committing the crime. Scottish law thus recognizes that delusional states often do not negate defendants’ intent to commit wrongful acts but provide reasons to form this intent.43 In English law, as a contrast, the criterion of understanding of the action has been interpreted in a more restrictive sense, referring only to the physical character of the act and not to its moral or legal quality.44 As a result, delusions are basically not relevant to the defendant’s understanding of the act, not even when the delusions may negate mens rea.

The most complicated, and hence debated, factor regarding the relevance of delusions concerns how delusions affect defendants’ understanding of the wrongfulness of their actions. In so far as defendants’ delusional motives render them incapable of understanding that their actions were wrong, they may in many jurisdictions be exempted from punishment. The discussion about the proper understanding of “wrong” in relation to criminal insanity has, in this regard, generated a vast amount of literature.12,45,–,51 It has been suggested that wrong should denote either the legal or the moral wrongfulness of the act or even both. According to the M’Naughten rules as interpreted in English law, wrong denotes unlawful. Only in so far as defendants did not understand that their actions were against the law can they be acquitted by reason of criminal insanity.52 This means that a defendant can be in a psychotic and delusional state of mind that influenced the act but still not qualify for being criminally insane.53,–,55 This narrow interpretation of wrong was established in England through the Windle case in 195256 and is also explicit in the model penal code, where it is stated that a person who “as a result of mental disease or defect…lacks substantial capacity either to appreciate the criminality [wrongfulness] of his conduct or to conform his conduct to the requirements of law.”57 At the same time, the reasoning in the Windle case and the restrictive interpretation of wrong have been criticized.58 For example, in 1975, the U.K. Butler Committee observed that it is a very narrow ground of exemption “since even persons who are grossly disturbed generally know that murder and arson are crimes” (Ref. 59, p 218). Moreover, many other countries that base their insanity defense on the M’Naughten rules have chosen a standard that denotes moral wrongfulness. The High Court of Australia in Stapleton v. The Queen60 already in 1952 expressly declined to follow Windle and instead concluded that the decisive question was whether defendants believed their act to be right according to the ordinary standard of reasonable people.60 In Canada, the Supreme Court initially followed Windle, but in 1990, in R v. Chaulk,61 the standard was reversed to that of wrong according to the ordinary moral standards of reasonable members of society. New Zealand has explicitly implemented such an interpretation of wrong in its Crimes Act.62

As the emphasis has thus turned to morally wrong in these jurisdictions, recent developments in English law have seemingly led to an even more restrictive standard for criminal insanity than before. According to the Keal case63 from 2022, wrong has been construed to mean that defendants must prove that they did not know their act was legally and morally wrong to succeed with the insanity defense. This means that defendants who delusionally believed that their acts were in accordance with the law but knew that they were morally wrong cannot be acquitted by reason of insanity.42

To give a feasible account of what it would mean not to know that the act is morally wrong, several scholars have modeled their accounts on what typically can constitute a justification for doing something that is under normal circumstances considered wrong. One reason to believe that hurting another human being is not wrong is that it is somehow justified. This line of reasoning is, for instance, expressed by Stephen J. Morse who explains:A person who delusionally believed that she was about to be killed by another person, and kills the other in the mistaken belief that she must do so to save her own life, does not rationally understand what she is doing. She of course knows that she is killing a human being and does so intentionally, but the rule against unjustifiable homicide will be ineffective because she delusionally believes that her action is justifiable. (Ref. 64, p 152)

Morse is referring to a legally valid justification, but if we are to interpret wrong as morally wrong, we must look for further moral justifications for committing an otherwise wrongful act, which is more challenging. To take the U.S. case of Andrea Yates65 as an example, the defense expert opined that Ms. Yates delusionally believed that, if she did not kill her children, they would suffer a far worse destiny. Her understanding of the murder was hence altruistic.50 This suggestion was controversial for several reasons, including that whether an altruistic motive morally justifies murder is dependent on what normative theory one endorses.

In sum, there are many controversies within the Anglo-American paradigm about how and why delusions are relevant to criminal insanity. They all have in common an emphasis on how the content of the defendants’ delusional beliefs relate to the specific crime. In our view, these controversies reveal profound challenges in specifying and applying legal standards for criminal insanity in a way that considers the complex manifestation of delusions. Delusions may be associated with functional impairments in different cognitive domains, and the extent to which a person’s general functional ability is affected by the delusions varies. Furthermore, because delusions also have a form, and because their content is influenced by experience, personality traits, and context, we cannot easily determine from their content how incapacitated a person experiencing delusions is to assess the veracity of the belief. In such a perspective, an emphasis on the content of the delusions may even result in unequal treatment before the law of equally mentally disordered and functionally impaired defendants.

To this point, the Norwegian approach brings different perspectives. Within Norwegian law, all that matters for insanity is if the defendant was impaired enough while committing the crime. This may, as we next discuss, provide an alternative way of linking criminal insanity to delusions.

The Alternative Approach of Norwegian Law

The Norwegian insanity doctrine differs from the insanity doctrines of most countries in so far as it does not operate with any requirement of a causal link between mental disorder and crime. The decisive question in the court’s evaluation is how mentally disordered the defendant was at the time of the act, disregarding if and how the defendant’s condition influenced the commission of the crime.66 In this way, insanity is associated with a sufficiently severe state of mental disorder and, as in other countries, criminal insanity is here especially associated with psychosis.2 This medical model approach, which has a long tradition in Norwegian law, became known to the wider international audience through the case concerning Anders Behring Breivik, who killed 77 people in Oslo and at Utøya on July 22, 2011.67 At that time, the Norwegian Penal Code Section 20 letter b defined criminal insanity in terms of being psychotic as a matter of having significantly impaired reality understanding (“The offender is not criminally responsible if, at the time of committing the act, he or she is…psychotic” (Ref. 68, Section 20 letter b, in the wording before January 10, 2020)). In the aftermath of the Breivik case, however, a law reform process was initiated, and a new rule in the Penal Code section came into force October 1, 2020.68,69 The psychosis criterion has now been replaced by criteria requiring that the defendant was “unaccountable due to” a “severely deviant state of mind” at the time of the act (Ref. 68, Section 20, second paragraph letter a). Now, the Norwegian rule requires a two-step evaluation.

The first step is to assess whether the defendant’s mental disorder at the time of the act qualifies as “a severely deviant state of mind” (Ref. 68, Section 20, second paragraph letter a) rather than referring to being “psychotic” as in the prior version. This criterion, in the same way as the previous one, primarily targets psychotic states of impaired reality understanding and requires obvious symptoms, such as delusions, at the time of the act. Other psychotic pathologies, such as hallucinations and disorganized thought process, are also relevant. In addition, the category includes other conditions equally serious as a psychotic state, measured in relation to how they affect the functional abilities and reality understanding of the defendant. In the bill from the Ministry of Justice, severe autism disorders and dementia conditions are mentioned as possible candidates (Ref. 70, p 76, 229) whereas personality disorders are excluded (Ref. 70, p 13, 67, 76). Except for personality disorders, a severely deviant state of mind can be the result of many different psychiatric and somatic disorders, such as brain tumors or infectious diseases, and the etiology of the condition is irrelevant. The focus on failures in functional abilities and reality understanding also allows for a severely deviant state of mind to be the result not only of one but of several coexisting disorders or dysfunctions.

If the first criterion is met, the second evaluation is whether the defendant was unaccountable because of this condition. In this evaluation, emphasis is given to the “degree of the person’s failure in appreciation of reality and functional capacity” (Ref. 68, Section 20, third paragraph). Still, there should be no evaluation of how the defendant’s disorder influenced the crime. The required evaluation of the defendant’s deficient appreciation of reality and the defendant’s functional capacity only concern the severity of the disorder at the time of the act considering the symptom load (Ref. 70, p 69). To illustrate, if the original M’Naughten case were adjudicated under current Norwegian law, the assessment would focus on whether he had a mental disorder at the time of the act that was sufficiently severe considering the impairments in cognitive functional abilities and reality understanding. In this assessment, his delusional beliefs about the criminal act would have been relevant only as proof to this matter in an overall assessment of his symptom load. Conversely, if the Breivik case were judged in England, the discussion of his alleged delusions would not only concern the presence and severity of his state of mental disorder at the time of the act but also whether his possibly delusional mental state influenced his understanding of his actions.

The Norwegian legislature has, however, provided the courts with a significant scope for discretion to ensure a reasonable and fair demarcation of criminal incapacity (Ref. 70, p 13, 69). Except for the almost unnecessary clarification from the Supreme Court that it is cognitive mental impairments that matter to criminal insanity,71 there is, to date, little legal clarification about the relevant impairments in reality understanding and functional capacity.65 The Ministry’s bill explains that a significant failure in one of these capacities can be sufficient (Ref. 70, p 230). At the same time, it is noted that “to have a delusion may not be sufficient” if the defendant’s general functioning is relatively good (Ref. 70, p 69). Interestingly, it also seems like the character of the crime may affect the assessment of the defendant’s accountability. With the Breivik case as the background, the Ministry states in its bill that “it can be hard for the public to accept that a relatively well-functioning person with the ability to plan and execute complicated crimes is not punished” (Ref. 70, p 69). The Supreme Court has followed this route and has stated that, for psychotic but cognitively well-functioning defendants with delusions, the question of whether they have planned their actions or not can be decisive for whether they should be acquitted or punished.71,72 In our view, this is a problematic approach that may lead to unequal treatment before the law, bearing in mind that severely psychotic persons may retain the ability to plan and commit seemingly complicated acts.73 Similar to the content focus in Anglo-American law, the result may be that equally impaired defendants are treated differently depending on the manifestation of their symptoms.

In this context, it should also be noted that the threshold for being acquitted by reason of criminal insanity is high also in Norway, resulting in sentencing many offenders with severe mental disorders and disabilities. Many of those that are acquitted by reason of insanity are also sentenced with special criminal sanctions of compulsory treatment to prevent them from committing new crimes, like dispositional measures that are used in Anglo-American systems.66 Here, an intriguing question is whether the different approaches to criminal insanity result in different forensic patient populations and thus different approaches to treatment and rehabilitation.

Still, as a regulative model for approaching the association between criminal insanity and delusions, the Norwegian approach carries some interesting perspectives. According to its rationale, it allows for a seriously disordered defendant to be acquitted, even without evidence that the disorder influenced the crime. Thus, a defendant can be acquitted even when the content of the delusions did not morally or legally justify the criminal act. They may also be punished when the delusions seemingly provided such a justification, whereas the defendant overall displayed good cognitive capacities at the time of the act. This approach evades focus on the link between disorder and crime and the content of delusions and suggests that the only consideration is whether a relevant and sufficiently severe disorder was present. Hence, the Norwegian model solves the causality problem by assuming that serious enough and legally relevant disorders, when present, generally impair cognitive capacities relevant to responsible actions. This seems reasonable, as there will always be epistemic insecurity in determining whether and how a mental disorder influences a crime.19

To this point, the Norwegian approach may have some advantages over the Anglo-American approach. The Norwegian approach will not differentiate between two defendants with similar degree of functional impairments who happen to have different manifestations of the content of their delusions and therefore seemingly different motivations for their crimes. It could be argued that equal treatment before the law is better ensured by an approach focusing on the severity of the functional impairment itself, at least if criminal insanity is to be associated to psychiatric notions of mental disorder. As explained, this is currently the case also in Anglo-American systems, because of the influence of forensic psychiatry in legal practice.2,3 Considering how challenging this association has become, the Norwegian approach asks us at least to reconsider the legal relevance of delusions. This, in turn, however, requires further work in clarifying the link between the manifestation of delusion and a sufficiently severe and legally relevant state of mental disorder.

Reconsidering the Relevance of Delusions

With the Norwegian approach as a point of entrance, the key question for the relevance of delusions is not how they influenced the commission of a specific crime but rather how delusions indicate a state of mental disorder that, when present at the time of the act, entails criminal insanity. To answer this question, we must concretize the relevant state of mental disorder as well as what we mean by delusions and, on this basis, explain their practical association, i.e., how delusions can be proof of legally relevant mental states. This is an ambitious task, and we will thus only sketch some possible ways forward for further discussion.

We propose, as a start, to investigate the possibility of utilizing psychiatric constructs as proxies for legally relevant functional impairments. In Norwegian law, insanity-relevant impairments have, as explained, become impairments in reality understanding or cognitive functional capacity. Thus, the question of the relevance of delusions becomes a question about how delusions relate to such impairments in a cognitive domain associated with the state of being psychotic. To concretize the relevance of delusions then requires us to explore what we know about how delusions may indicate or correlate with cognitive impairments, especially in terms of reality understanding.

This is not a straightforward exercise, not least because it asks for investigations in mental health research. The challenge is that impaired reality understanding and cognitive impairments are subject to different definitions and interpretations. Both cognitive impairment and impaired reality testing are broad psychological terms that are also core features of schizophrenia.74 It is thus to a large degree unclear both how relevant functional impairments should be defined and how they relate to psychiatric symptoms, such as delusions.75 Moreover, also with given definitions of the cognitive impairments in question, it is challenging to disentangle if and how delusions affect or are a sign of these impairments.

The question becomes even more demanding as the law must decide if the defendant is disordered enough. In other words, given that delusions are relevant per se, we need to understand them according to a severity spectrum of mental disorder. The challenge is then how we should define and assess this spectrum. One possible approach is here provided by the continuum model of psychosis, where some scholars argue that delusions exist along a continuum from normal experiences and thought processes to severe psychopathology.76,77 Following this line of thought, one may argue that the functional impairments delusions indicate could be assessed as more severe the more the content deviates from normal beliefs. The most severe forms of delusions may indicate not only an incapacity to form justifiable beliefs but also a severely impaired ability to perceive reality accurately. Focus is again on the content of delusions, but not with respect to how it is related to the crime (as beliefs, motivation, and possible justifications) but to how extraordinary the beliefs are in relation to what is deemed as normal in a clinical sense.

The continuum model of psychosis has, however, been criticized for being unscientific and posing challenges to the need for setting thresholds for more or less severe psychosis symptoms, such as delusions.78,79 An alternative approach to assess the severity of a state of mental disorder is provided through what are called Schneiderian first-rank symptoms (e.g., delusions of thought insertion or of being controlled or the original concept of delusional perception). Originally thought to be pathognomonic for schizophrenia, these symptoms presuppose a radical qualitative change of consciousness that fundamentally involves a disorder of the self (“Ichstörungen” or self-disorders)80 that is understood as distinctly different from normal beliefs in both form and content.81 This approach provides a more global perspective on certain types of delusions as indicators of mental disorder that highlight the fundamental breakdown of the delusional person’s capacity to perceive reality accurately, which may affect the person’s entire cognitive functioning. Intuitively, this seems to provide a possible link between delusions and a sufficiently severe and legally relevant state of mental disorder.

A practical challenge is that the first-rank symptom concepts are not included in the DSM-5 and minimized in the International Classification of Diseases (ICD)-11, which challenges translation to diagnostic categories that are the common basis for forensic experts in criminal proceedings. At the same time, this challenge should not be exaggerated as the severity dimension of delusions is not necessarily linked to the presence of a specific diagnosis and diagnoses are not, as such, legally relevant. More challenging is the fact that the Schneiderian first-rank symptoms exclude certain types of delusions. For example, first-rank symptoms do not include the delusions of persecution, reference, or grandiosity (in their pure form). The omission of these forms of delusion could, to some extent, be seen as a return to a content focus, but again, not in relation to the crime. It is the type of content (persecutory) rather than the specific content (X is spying on me and trying to kill me) that is of relevance. Moreover, the fact that the Schneiderian first-rank symptom has a specificity for schizophrenia introduces a diagnostic categorical bias where, in practice, delusions as part of other disorders (i.e., affective or other psychotic disorders) would be excluded. This does not align with our understanding of the legal relevance of mental disorders, which is based on the extent of functional impairments rather than on specific diagnoses.

The ultimate question of what kind of functional impairment is relevant and sufficient is inevitably normative. After all, we cannot define the threshold of insanity as if it is related to natural distinctions between different mental categories. From psychiatry’s perspective, symptoms and functional impairments occur on a continuum, whereas the threshold between the responsible and nonresponsible must be defined by the law. Furthermore, one should be cautious to attach decisive weight to delusions as symptoms of mental disorder. At least, we must keep in mind that deviations from reasonable beliefs are commonplace in the nonclinical population. It is also well known how difficult it can be to distinguish psychotic delusions from extreme ideas82,83 and that defendants with extremist views can experience a mental disorder. These observations hold regardless of specific construction of criminal insanity.

A tentative conclusion is thus that we need to clarify the legal relevance of delusions within a legal and normative domain and thus to look beyond delusions as broad psychiatric constructs. Instead of using psychiatric constructs as proxies for criminal insanity, we need to seek clear normative definitions of the relevant functional impairments. In other words, we must return to the law’s concept of criminal insanity and operationalize and possibly revisit the relevance of delusions through this lens. One key to such operationalization is, in our view, empirical study of legal reasoning in concrete cases. In addition, philosophy, as well as mental health research, can help to illuminate law’s normative and empirical assumptions and their consistency with the knowledge perspectives to which the law relates.19 It may be that, in the end, this will lead us to move beyond focusing on the content of delusions and even beyond the paradigmatic legal view of the relevance of delusions and mental disorders as such.

Future Directions for Law and Research

We started by outlining the problem of linking criminal insanity to the psychiatric construct of delusions. We have argued that the paradigmatic focus on the content of delusions raises several problems and suggested that the Norwegian approach provides an alternative point of entrance to the legal relevance of delusions as it does not involve any causality assessment and therefore evades the focus on delusional content. We have further shown that this approach reveals deeper problems requiring clarification. In fact, there seems to be a more profound problem in law’s association between criminal insanity and mental disorders, which consists in the unclarity in this very association. This challenge appears to be present across different legal systems with significantly different insanity doctrines, and it largely seems to be related to how contemporary criminal insanity doctrines and related legal practices relate to psychiatry.84

It is fundamental for the criminal insanity doctrine to identify defendants who should not be blamed and punished. From a constitutional point of view, the most important consideration may even not be precisely how we define the threshold for criminal insanity but rather that this threshold is defined clearly enough to secure equal treatment before the law. Also in such a perspective, it is imperative that we challenge the current paradigmatic emphasis on the content of delusions as evidence of criminal insanity. We hope, therefore, that our paper can stimulate research engagement and discussion about the relevance of delusions for criminal insanity and more generally about why and how mental disorders are and should be relevant to criminal law.

Acknowledgments

The paper is related to a project, DIMENSIONS, funded by the research council of Norway (project code 314840).

Footnotes

  • Disclosures of financial or other potential conflicts of interest: None.

  • © 2025 American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law

References

  1. 1.↵
    1. Mackay R,
    2. Brookbanks W
    , editors. The Insanity Defence: International and Comparative Perspectives. Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press; 2022
  2. 2.↵
    1. Moore MS
    . The quest for a responsible responsibility test: Norwegian insanity law after Breivik. Crim Law Philos. 2015 Mar; 9(4):645–93
    OpenUrl
  3. 3.↵
    1. White MD
    1. Wondemaghen M
    . Insanity constructs. In White MD, editor. The Insanity Defense: Multidisciplinary Views on Its History, Trends and Controversies. London, U.K.: Praeger; 2017. p. 133–52
  4. 4.↵
    1. Crocker AG,
    2. Nicholls TL,
    3. Seto MC
    et al. The national trajectory project of individuals found not criminally responsible on account of mental disorder in Canada. Part 2: The people behind the label. Can J Psychiatry. 2015 Mar; 60(3):106–16
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  5. 5.↵
    1. Tsimploulis G,
    2. Niveau G,
    3. Eytan A
    et al. Schizophrenia and criminal responsibility: A systematic review. J Nerv Ment Dis. 2018 May; 206(5):370–7
    OpenUrlPubMed
  6. 6.↵
    1. Skeie CA,
    2. Rasmussen K
    . Assessment of causal associations between illness and criminal acts in those who are acquitted by reason of insanity. Tidsskr Nor Laegeforen. 2015 Feb; 135(4):327–30
    OpenUrlPubMed
  7. 7.↵
    1. Johnston L
    . Delusions, moral incapacity, and the case for moral wrongfulness. Ind LJ. 2022; 97(1):297–363
    OpenUrl
  8. 8.↵
    1. Løvgren PJ,
    2. Laake P,
    3. Reitan SK,
    4. Narud K
    . Assessing psychotic symptoms in forensic evaluations of criminal responsibility—A pilot study using positive and negative syndrome scale. J Forensic Psychiatry Psychol. 2020 May; 31(4):490–502
    OpenUrl
  9. 9.↵
    World Health Organization. International Statistical Classification of Diseases and Related Health Problems [Internet]; 2019. Available from: https://icd.who.int/browse11/l-m/en. Accessed March 1, 2024
  10. 10.↵
    American Psychiatric Association. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Fifth Edition, Text Revision. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association, 2022
  11. 11.↵
    1. Johnston EL,
    2. Leahey VT
    . The status and legitimacy of M’Naghten’s insane delusion rule. UC Davis L Rev. 2020 April; 54:1777–852
    OpenUrl
  12. 12.↵
    1. Deigh J,
    2. Dolinko D
    1. Sinnott-Armstrong W,
    2. Levy K
    . Insanity defenses. In Deigh J, Dolinko D, editors. The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Criminal Law. New York, NY: Oxford University Press; 2011. p. 299–334
  13. 13.↵
    1. Moore MS.
    Law and Psychiatry: Rethinking the Relationship. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press; 1984
  14. 14.↵
    1. Morse SJ
    . Rationality and responsibility. S Cal L Rev. 2000; 74:251–68
    OpenUrl
  15. 15.↵
    1. Cornish DB,
    2. Clarke RV
    1. Norrie A
    . Practical reasoning and criminal responsibility: A jurisprudential approach. In Cornish DB, Clarke RV, editors. The Reasoning Criminal. New York, NY: Routledge; 2017. p. 217–30
  16. 16.↵
    1. Gröning L
    . Regulating criminal unaccountability—From concepts to defensible legal standards. Bergen Journal of Criminal Law & Criminal Justice. 2024; 12(1):1–31
    OpenUrl
  17. 17.↵
    1. Brink DO
    . Situationism, responsibility, and fair opportunity. Soc Phil Pol. 2013; 30(1-2):121–49
    OpenUrl
  18. 18.↵
    1. Moratti S,
    2. Patterson D
    1. Morse SJ
    . Legal insanity in the age of neuroscience. In Moratti S, Patterson D, editors. Legal Insanity and the Brain: Science, Law and European Courts. Oxford, U.K.: Hart Publishing; 2016. p. 239–76
  19. 19.↵
    1. Crofts T,
    2. Kennefick L,
    3. Loughnan A
    1. Gröning L
    . Criminal insanity and mental disorder: Reconsidering the relation. In Crofts T, Kennefick L, Loughnan A, editors. International Handbook on Criminal Responsibility, London, U.K.: Routledge; Forthcoming
  20. 20.↵
    1. Lernestedt C,
    2. Matravers M
    , editors. The Criminal Law’s Person. London, U.K.: Bloomsbury Publishing, 2022
  21. 21.↵
    1. Heilskov SER,
    2. Urfer-Parnas A,
    3. Nordgaard J
    . Delusions in the general population: A systematic review with emphasis on methodology. Schizophr Res. 2020 Feb; 216:48–55
    OpenUrlPubMed
  22. 22.↵
    1. Peralta V,
    2. Cuesta MJ
    . An empirical study of five sets of diagnostic criteria for delusional disorder. Schizophr Res. 2019 Jul; 209:164–70
    OpenUrlPubMed
  23. 23.↵
    1. Scheid TL,
    2. Brown TN
    1. Peterson C
    . Psychological approaches to mental illness. In Scheid TL, Brown TN, editors. A Handbook for the Study of Mental Health: Social Contexts, Theories, and Systems. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press; 2009. p. 89–105
  24. 24.↵
    1. Clark LA,
    2. Cuthbert B,
    3. Lewis-Fernández R
    et al. Three approaches to understanding and classifying mental disorder: ICD-11, DSM-5, and the National Institute of Mental Health’s Research Domain Criteria (RDoC). Psychol Sci Public Interest. 2017 Sep; 18(2):72–145
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  25. 25.↵
    1. Freeman D,
    2. Garety PA.
    Paranoia: The Psychology of Persecutory Delusions. Hove, East Sussex: Psychology Press; 2004
  26. 26.↵
    1. Spitzer M
    . On defining delusions. Compr Psychiatry. 1990 Sep-Oct; 31(5):377–97
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  27. 27.↵
    1. Jaspers K.
    General Psychopathology. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press; 1963
  28. 28.↵
    1. Feyaerts J,
    2. Henriksen MG,
    3. Vanheule S
    et al. Delusions beyond beliefs: A critical overview of diagnostic, aetiological, and therapeutic schizophrenia research from a clinical-phenomenological perspective. Lancet Psychiatry. 2021 Jan; 8(3):237–49
    OpenUrlPubMed
  29. 29.↵
    1. Pierre JM
    . Integrating non-psychiatric models of delusion-like beliefs into forensic psychiatric assessment. J Am Acad Psychiatry Law. 2019 Jun; 47(2):171–9
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  30. 30.↵
    1. Mullen R,
    2. Linscott RJ
    . A comparison of delusions and overvalued ideas. J Nerv Ment Dis. 2010 Jan; 198(1):35–8
    OpenUrlPubMed
  31. 31.↵
    1. Cermolacce M,
    2. Sass L,
    3. Parnas J
    . What is bizarre in bizarre delusions? A critical review. Schizophr Bull. 2010 Jul; 36(4):667–79
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  32. 32.↵
    1. McAllister-Williams RH
    . The description of primary delusions: Confusion in standard texts and among clinicians. Psychiatr Bull. 1997; 21(6):346–9
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  33. 33.↵
    1. Nielsen KM,
    2. Nordgaard J,
    3. Gram Henriksen M
    . Delusional perception revisited. Psychopathology. 2022; 55(6):325–34
    OpenUrlPubMed
  34. 34.↵
    1. Garety PA,
    2. Freeman D
    . The past and future of delusions research: From the inexplicable to the treatable. Br J Psychiatry. 2013 Nov; 203(5):327–33
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  35. 35.↵
    1. Bebbington P,
    2. Freeman D
    . Transdiagnostic extension of delusions: Schizophrenia and beyond. Schizophr Bull. 2017 Mar; 43(2):273–82
    OpenUrlPubMed
  36. 36.↵
    1. Diaconescu AO,
    2. Hauke DJ,
    3. Borgwardt S
    . Models of persecutory delusions: A mechanistic insight into the early stages of psychosis. Mol Psychiatry. 2019 Sep; 24(9):1258–67
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  37. 37.↵
    1. Sterzer P,
    2. Adams RA,
    3. Fletcher P
    et al. The predictive coding account of psychosis. Biol Psychiatry. 2018 Nov; 84(9):634–43
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  38. 38.↵
    1. Bansal S,
    2. Bae G-Y,
    3. Robinson BM
    et al. Association between failures in perceptual updating and the severity of psychosis in schizophrenia. JAMA Psychiatry. 2022 Feb; 79(2):169–77
    OpenUrlPubMed
  39. 39.↵
    1. Bortolotti L
    1. Upthegrove R
    . Delusional beliefs in the clinical context. In Bortolotti L, editor. Delusions in Context. London, U.K.: Palgrave Macmillan, Cham; 2018. p. 1–34
  40. 40.↵
    1. Appelbaum PS,
    2. Robbins PC,
    3. Vesselinov R
    . Persistence and stability of delusions over time. Compr Psychiatry. 2004 Sep-Oct; 45(5):317–24
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  41. 41.↵
    1. Bortolotti L,
    2. Broome MR,
    3. Mameli M
    . Delusions and responsibility for action: Insights from the Breivik case. Neuroethics. 2014; 7(3):377–82
    OpenUrlPubMed
  42. 42.↵
    1. Vars FE
    . Of death and delusion: What survives Kahler v. Kansas? U Pa L Rev Online. 2020 October; 169:90–9
    OpenUrl
  43. 43.↵
    1. Mackay R,
    2. Brookbanks W
    1. Maher G
    . The mental disorder defence in Scots law. In Mackay R, Brookbanks W, editors. The Insanity Defence: International and Comparative Perspectives. Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press; 2022. p. 86–7
  44. 44.↵
    1. Mackay R,
    2. Brookbanks W
    1. Mackay R
    . The insanity defence in English law. In Mackay R, Brookbanks W, editors. The Insanity Defence: International and Comparative Perspectives. Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press; 2022. p. 21–44
  45. 45.↵
    1. Bloch KE
    . Untangling right from wrong in insanity law: Of dogs, wolves & God. Hastings L J. 2022; 73(4):947–74
    OpenUrl
  46. 46.↵
    1. Keal RV
    . Wrongdoing in the M’Naghten rules. J Crim L. 2022; 86(2):130–3
    OpenUrl
  47. 47.↵
    1. Mason J
    . What’s wrong with wrongfulness? Reconsidering the wrongness limb of the insanity defence. J Crime & Crim Behav. 2021; 1(1):21–5
    OpenUrl
  48. 48.↵
    1. Yakush BA,
    2. Wolbransky M
    . Insanity and the definition of wrongfulness in California. J Forensic Psychol Pract. 2013 Jul; 13(4):355–72
    OpenUrl
  49. 49.↵
    People v. Stress, 205 Cal. App. 3d 1259 (Cal. Ct. App. 1988)
  50. 50.↵
    1. Michalopoulos C
    . Filling in the holes of the insanity defense: The Andrea Yates case and the need for a new prong. Va J Soc Pol'y & L. 2022; 10(3):383–409
    OpenUrl
  51. 51.↵
    1. Bloch KE,
    2. Gould J
    . Legal indeterminacy in insanity cases: Clarifying wrongfulness and applying a triadic approach to forensic evaluations. Hastings L J. 2016; 67:913–56
    OpenUrl
  52. 52.↵
    R. v. M’Naghten (1843) 8 E.R. 718 (Eng.)
  53. 53.↵
    R. v. Valdo Calocane, [2024] Nott CC U20231322
  54. 54.↵
    R. v. Usman, [2013] EWCA Crim 468
  55. 55.↵
    1. Mackay R
    . Case commentary: Insanity: R. v. Usman Court of Appeal (Criminal Division). Crim L Rev. 2023; 9:600–5
    OpenUrl
  56. 56.↵
    R. v. Windle (1952) 2 QB 826
  57. 57.↵
    Model Penal Code. § 4.01[Internet]; 1985. Available from: https://www.law.upenn.edu/faculty/paul-robinson/clrgcodes/MPC.html. Accessed June 16, 2024
  58. 58.↵
    1. Manwaring J
    . Windle revisited. Crim L Rev. 2018; 12:987–92
    OpenUrl
  59. 59.↵
    Committee on Mentally Abnormal Offenders. The Report of the Committee on Mentally Abnormal Offenders (Cmnd 6244) [Internet]; 1975. Available from: https://wellcomecollection.org/works/steazp4r. Accessed June 16, 2024
  60. 60.↵
    Stapleton v The Queen (1952) 86 CLR 358 (Austl.)
  61. 61.↵
    R. v. Chaulk, [1990] 3 S.C.R. 1303 (Can.)
  62. 62.↵
    New Zealand Legislation. Crimes Act 1961 [Internet]; 1961. Available from:https://www.legislation.govt.nz/act/public/1961/0043/latest/DLM330444.html. Accessed June 18, 2024
  63. 63.↵
    R. v. Keal [2022] EWCA (Crim) 341 (Eng.)
  64. 64.↵
    1. Morse SJ
    . Craziness and criminal responsibility. Behav Sci & L. 1999; 17(2):147–64
    OpenUrl
  65. 65.↵
    1. Resnick PJ
    . The Andrea Yates case: Insanity on trial. Clev St L Rev. 2007; 55(2):147–56
    OpenUrl
  66. 66.↵
    1. Mackay R,
    2. Brookbanks W
    1. Gröning L
    . Criminal insanity in Norwegian law. In Mackay R, Brookbanks W, editors. The Insanity Defence: International and Comparative Perspectives. Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press; 2022. p. 295–315
  67. 67.↵
    Lovdata. Judgment of July 22nd, 2012.08.24 (TOSLO-2011-188627-24- RG-2012-1153) [Internet]; 2024. Available from: https://lovdata.no/info/22juli. Accessed June 20, 2024
  68. 68.↵
    Lovdata. The Norwegian Penal code (LOV-2005-05-20-28) [Internet]; 2024. Available from: https://www.lovdata.no/doccument/NLE/lov/2005-20-28. Accessed June 20, 2024
  69. 69.↵
    1. Gröning L
    . Has Norway abandoned its medical model? Thoughts about the criminal insanity reform post 22 July. Crim L Rev. 2021; 3:191–202
  70. 70.↵
    Regjeringen.no. Bill (legislative proposal) from the Ministry of Justice and Public security, Prop. 154 L (2016–2017) [Internet]; 2024. Available from: https://www.regjeringen.no. Accessed June 20, 2024
  71. 71.↵
    Lovdata. Supreme Court Judgment 2023.06.29 (HR-2023-1243-A) [Internet]; 2024. Available from: https://lovdata.no/dokument/HRSTR/avgjorelse/hr-2023-1243-a. Accessed June 20, 2024
  72. 72.↵
    Lovdata. Supreme Court Judgment 2023.06.29 (HR- 2023-1242-A) [Internet]; 2024. Available from: https://lovdata.no/dokument/HRSTR/avgjorelse/hr-2023-1242-a. Accessed June 20 2024
  73. 73.↵
    1. Gröning L,
    2. Melle KH
    . En kommentar til HR-2023-1242-A og HR-2023-1243-A: Planlegging som premiss for (u)tilregnelighet og rettens bruk av diagnoser. [Planning as argument for (un)accountability and the court’s use of diagnoses]. Jussens Venner. 2024; 59(3):167–87
    OpenUrl
  74. 74.↵
    1. Green MF
    . Cognitive impairment and functional outcome in schizophrenia and bipolar disorder. J Clin Psychiatry. 2006; 67(10):e12
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  75. 75.↵
    1. Gröning L,
    2. Haukvik UK,
    3. Morse SJ,
    4. Radovic S
    . Remodelling criminal insanity: Exploring philosophical, legal, and medical premises of the medical model used in Norwegian law. Int ’l J L & Psychiatry. 2022 Mar-Apr; 81:101776
    OpenUrl
  76. 76.↵
    1. Nuevo R,
    2. Chatterji S,
    3. Verdes E
    et al. The continuum of psychotic symptoms in the general population: A cross-national study. Schizophr Bull. 2012 May; 38(3):475–85
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  77. 77.↵
    1. van Os J,
    2. Linscott RJ,
    3. Myin-Germeys I
    et al. A systematic review and meta-analysis of the psychosis continuum: Evidence for a psychosis proneness-persistence-impairment model of psychotic disorder. Psychol Med. 2009; 39(2):179–95
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  78. 78.↵
    1. Lawrie SM,
    2. Hall J,
    3. McIntosh AM
    et al. The ‘continuum of psychosis’: Scientifically unproven and clinically impractical. Br J Psychiatry. 2010 Dec; 197(6):423–5
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  79. 79.↵
    1. David AS
    . Why we need more debate on whether psychotic symptoms lie on a continuum with normality. Psychol Med. 2010 Dec; 40(12):1935–42
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  80. 80.↵
    1. Schneider K.
    Clinical Psychopathology. New York, NY: Grune & Stratton; 1959
  81. 81.↵
    1. Nordgaard J,
    2. Henriksen MG,
    3. Berge J,
    4. Siersbæk Nilsson L
    . Associations between self-disorders and first- rank symptoms: An empirical study. Psychopathology. 2020; 53(2):103–10
    OpenUrlPubMed
  82. 82.↵
    1. Rahman T,
    2. Hartz SM,
    3. Xiong W
    et al. Extreme overvalued beliefs. J Am Acad Psychiatry Law. 2020 Sep; 48(3):319–26
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  83. 83.↵
    1. Schwartz HI
    . The mind of the mass school shooter. J Am Acad Psychiatry Law. 2023 Sep; 51(3):314–9
    OpenUrlFREE Full Text
  84. 84.↵
    1. Gröning L,
    2. Dimitrova S
    . Criminal insanity in Bulgaria and Norway: Analysing the prospect of a common approach. Int J Law Psychiatry. 2023 Mar-Apr; 87:101866
    OpenUrlPubMed
PreviousNext
Back to top

In this issue

Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online: 53 (1)
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online
Vol. 53, Issue 1
1 Mar 2025
  • Table of Contents
  • Index by author
Print
Download PDF
Article Alerts
Sign In to Email Alerts with your Email Address
Email Article

Thank you for your interest in recommending The Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law site.

NOTE: We only request your email address so that the person you are recommending the page to knows that you wanted them to see it, and that it is not junk mail. We do not capture any email address.

Enter multiple addresses on separate lines or separate them with commas.
Reconsidering the Relationship Between Criminal Insanity and Delusions
(Your Name) has forwarded a page to you from Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law
(Your Name) thought you would like to see this page from the Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law web site.
CAPTCHA
This question is for testing whether or not you are a human visitor and to prevent automated spam submissions.
Citation Tools
Reconsidering the Relationship Between Criminal Insanity and Delusions
Linda Gröning, Susanna Radovic, Unn K. Haukvik
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online Mar 2025, 53 (1) 35-44; DOI: 10.29158/JAAPL.240085-24

Citation Manager Formats

  • BibTeX
  • Bookends
  • EasyBib
  • EndNote (tagged)
  • EndNote 8 (xml)
  • Medlars
  • Mendeley
  • Papers
  • RefWorks Tagged
  • Ref Manager
  • RIS
  • Zotero

Share
Reconsidering the Relationship Between Criminal Insanity and Delusions
Linda Gröning, Susanna Radovic, Unn K. Haukvik
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online Mar 2025, 53 (1) 35-44; DOI: 10.29158/JAAPL.240085-24
del.icio.us logo Twitter logo Facebook logo Mendeley logo
  • Tweet Widget
  • Facebook Like
  • Google Plus One

Jump to section

  • Article
    • Abstract
    • Criminal Insanity and Delusions
    • The Anglo-American Approach
    • The Alternative Approach of Norwegian Law
    • Reconsidering the Relevance of Delusions
    • Future Directions for Law and Research
    • Acknowledgments
    • Footnotes
    • References
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF

Related Articles

Cited By...

More in this TOC Section

  • A Forensic Science-Based Model for Identifying and Mitigating Forensic Mental Health Expert Biases
  • Bias in Peer Review of Forensic Psychiatry Publications
Show more Regular Article

Similar Articles

Keywords

  • criminal law
  • criminal responsibility
  • delusions
  • insanity defense

Site Navigation

  • Home
  • Current Issue
  • Ahead of Print
  • Archive
  • Information for Authors
  • About the Journal
  • Editorial Board
  • Feedback
  • Alerts

Other Resources

  • Academy Website
  • AAPL Meetings
  • AAPL Annual Review Course

Reviewers

  • Peer Reviewers

Other Publications

  • AAPL Practice Guidelines
  • AAPL Newsletter
  • AAPL Ethics Guidelines
  • AAPL Amicus Briefs
  • Landmark Cases

Customer Service

  • Cookie Policy
  • Reprints and Permissions
  • Order Physical Copy

Copyright © 2025 by The American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law