Skip to main content

Main menu

  • Home
  • Current Issue
  • Ahead of Print
  • Past Issues
  • Info for
    • Authors
    • Print Subscriptions
  • About
    • About the Journal
    • About the Academy
    • Editorial Board
  • Feedback
  • Alerts
  • AAPL

User menu

  • Alerts

Search

  • Advanced search
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law
  • AAPL
  • Alerts
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law

Advanced Search

  • Home
  • Current Issue
  • Ahead of Print
  • Past Issues
  • Info for
    • Authors
    • Print Subscriptions
  • About
    • About the Journal
    • About the Academy
    • Editorial Board
  • Feedback
  • Alerts
OtherREGULAR ARTICLE

Commentary: It’s About the Fundamentals

John L. Young
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online December 2006, 34 (4) 479-481;
John L. Young
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • Article
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF
Loading

Abstract

Recent actions by the American Psychiatric Association, the American Medical Association, and the American Psychological Association document a growing consensus that health professionals should not become directly involved in hostile interrogations. Challenging questions remain regarding the permissibility of indirect involvement, such as training directed toward promoting the humanity of interrogation procedures and the reliability of their results. A fundamental challenge comes from those who hold that a physician may relinquish the caring role and proceed to disregard medical ethics altogether. Some experts have even gone so far as to allege that all existing rules of medical ethics are baseless statements and thus cannot bind anyone. Forensic psychiatrists’ continuing contributions to this debate are critical.

Our colleague Jeffrey Janofsky1 did not write his essay for the faint of heart. The first few seconds of reading it jolted me with a re-experiencing of the revulsion I had felt upon reading a police report more than a decade ago. Despite knowing full well that the hospitalized infant victim was beyond any hope of survival, the officer relentlessly plied the suspect for details of his crime. He pretended that the information would be passed along immediately to help the doctors and nurses save the victim’s life. My client in this case, the defense attorney, explained that the interrogation was perfectly legal, in accord with the U.S. Supreme Court. The case of Colorado v. Connelly2 came readily to mind, and upon review, I found that its text had significance I had never suspected and have never forgotten.

Janofsky’s essay opens with a slippery-slope argument: that engaging even indirectly with those who use damaging deception exposes us to the risk that we will become participants in such acts. As the reader proceeds, a virtual landscape of slippery slopes comes into view. There is the first, which begins with harsh but (allegedly) acceptable techniques and ends with outright and already prohibited torture. Another begins with conventional control of an interview and descends to overwhelming manipulation by the interrogator to extract more information than the victim intends to reveal. A further and less precipitous slope underlies the suggestion that because some consultants have obviously transgressed—sharing medical records with interrogators, for example—none of us should ever become involved at all.

Slippery-slope arguments can be informative and compelling, but critical issues require more scrutiny. Rightly, Janofsky turns to expert interpretation of existing ethics principles and guidelines. In summary, he cites the argument by Appelbaum3 that respect for persons outranks the search for truth, the prohibition recommended by Simon and Wettstein4 against any form of manipulation of examinees, and the point made by Candilis5 that the power differential between the individual and the state requires protecting the examinee. Janofsky also recounts the positions against participation in torture taken by the American Medical Association (AMA), the American Psychiatric Association (APA), and the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law (AAPL).6,7

Current Views From Three Associations

Janofsky’s foresight is apparent. After the Journal accepted his manuscript, first the APA and then the AMA promulgated closely similar declarations supporting his position. Zonana8 reports the pertinent history in meticulous detail, including a list of seven points that were significantly influential in producing a united voice for the house of medicine on this challenging subject. He includes the APA text (except for a footnote defining interrogation). He specifically mentions the importance of AAPL’s successful efforts to increase its voice within the AMA.

Following two years of discussion and exchanges of drafts between its Assembly of District Branches and its Board of Trustees, the APA adopted at its Toronto meeting in May 2006 a Position Statement on Detainee Interrogations.9 Paul Appelbaum as chair of the joint Board-Assembly Work Group adroitly summarized the key distinction between forensic evaluations that seek to assess the examinee’s mental state and interrogations that seek unintended disclosures from its subject. As a position statement, the document has less weight than a medical ethics principle or annotation, but does speak representatively for the organization. It affirms the points in Janofsky’s essay, including a ban on involvement in torture and a prohibition of either direct or indirect participation in interrogation. However, it appears more permissive in regard to providing training for police and investigators in legitimate areas of psychiatric expertise. Also included are a ban on disclosure of medical records to interrogators, and a duty to report torture whether past, current, or planned.

For its part the AMA House of Delegates adopted as policy a report of its Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs in Chicago in June 2006,9 quickly following the APA action. Like its APA counterpart, this policy describes and condemns the direct participation by physicians in interrogations, along with the disclosure of medical records. It also includes the reporting requirement. Its text is also to be found in Zonana’s report.8 It is likely that a prohibition reflecting both documents will be incorporated into The Principles of Medical Ethics With Annotations Especially Applicable to Psychiatry,10 possibly under Section 7 which currently provides that “psychiatrists shall not participate in torture.” Such a prohibition would be expected once there has been adequate time for a consensus to emerge among mental health professionals and the lay public.

Zonana8 mentions in passing a “broader” July 2005 position paper of the American Psychological Association (APA). Stephen Behnke,11 director of the APA’s Ethics Office, convincingly points out that its position closely parallels the AMA document. Both are based on an ethics analysis aimed at striking a balance between doing no harm and fulfilling responsibilities to society, in particular by using their expertise to aid in preventing harm. In its turn, the AMA document refers to balancing obligations to individuals with obligations to protect third parties and the public.10

In contrast, Behnke11 states that his group’s position appears to be derived solely from the single principle against doing harm. In any event, the three documents are far more notable for the extensiveness of their agreement than for differences of any significance. Behnke’s report is also important for its description of “behavioral drift,” the deviation under stress by interrogators from ethically acceptable techniques to forbidden coercive behavior. According to Behnke, psychologists have the training required to observe and intervene to prevent this phenomenon and are rightly permitted to undertake such a role. He concludes by affirming that his group’s board of directors recognizes “deeply felt and diverse opinions” among its membership and therefore encourages continuing debate.

Contrasting Philosophical Reflections

Owing to our tendency to focus reflexively on the consultant’s role, it is worth keeping in mind that the majority of professionals affected by the discussion at hand are in fact our colleagues serving in the military. Clark12 sensitively undertakes an analysis of what they face in their daily work, recognizing that the present situation is in fact serious and urgent. He begins with the subtle suggestion that the proceedings associated with Abu Ghraib and Guantanamo Bay are precariously close to those of the Nazi death camps. He begins with a detailed review of dual loyalty conflicts, showing how endemic and widespread they have become in both civil society and in the military experience. Several historic declarations come into play, along with the lack of needed training for those who are pulled forcefully by loyalties to their patients, their fellow soldiers, and the chain of command. Several medical specialties are involved, with both common and unique vulnerabilities. Demands also arise from differences in location, whether Iraq, Afghanistan, or elsewhere.

More seriously, Clark12 reports a Pentagon argument that, as “behavioral scientists,” medical members of the military are “not treating patients” and are therefore free to ignore medical ethics. He goes on to cite examples of conduct that he sees as violating the principles of respect for persons, beneficence, nonmaleficence, and justice. He calls for an independent board of inquiry to evaluate the abuses he describes, with specific suggestions for the membership of such a board. In addition, he urges proper human rights training, a military ethics committee to provide personnel with ongoing guidance and support, and vigorous follow-up by the professional associations.

Allhoff,13 after researching physician involvement in hostile interrogations as a senior fellow at the Institute for Ethics for the AMA and leaving for academe, writes to proffer a view challenging not only Clark’s view but also Janofsky’s and those of the three professional associations. Allhoff argues for a narrowed definition of torture and goes on to assert an ethical obligation to be present at such torture sessions. In all apparent seriousness, he bases his conclusion on both beneficence and nonmaleficence. Then, using forensic psychiatry, occupational health, and public health as accepted examples of dual loyalties, he moves to include also physician participation in torture. Any duty owed to the interrogatee is superseded by those owed to national security.

Next, Allhoff13 sets aside the dual loyalties argument in favor of “the more extreme claim that there are no [his emphasis] medical duties or responsibilities that the medically trained interrogator has to the interrogatee….” Such an interrogator, he states, is “not a physician at all.” He finds support for this assertion in the prerogative stated in Section 6 of the AMA Principles of Medical Ethics10 to choose one’s patients. (The reader should take due notice here of Allhoff’s shift in language from participant to interrogator.)

Finally, Allhoff13 casts aside ethics principles as “merely statements” [his emphasis], without philosophical merit, since there is no argument on which they are based. Correspondingly, he claims that the AMA has authority only in regard to medical matters. He adds that moral duty cannot be held to follow from the possession of knowledge. As an analogy, he remarks that knowledge of chemistry does not in itself confer an obligation not to make chemical weapons. At the outset of his presentation, Allhoff points out that he assumes for the sake of discussion that hostile interrogations are morally justifiable, including acknowledged torture. Since he must be aware of the medical ethics prohibitions against torture, one almost has to wonder whether his piece is but a clever tongue-in-cheek reductio ad absurdum.

Conclusion

Has the slippery slope given way to free fall? It is up to us to decide. The interrogation discussion has implications for how we sort out the relationship between forensic psychiatry and the practice of medicine. It carries further to the fundamentals of medicine itself. On what do we base our canons of medical ethics? Presumably something beyond the content of medical knowledge gives rise to the duties associated with having received from society the privilege of becoming a physician. The current lively dialogue in matters of forensic psychiatric ethics will assuredly continue. We owe Jeffrey Janofsky our gratitude for his stimulating contribution.

  • American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law

References

  1. ↵
    Janofsky JS: Lies and coercion: why psychiatrists should not participate in police and intelligence interrogations. J Am Acad Psychiatry Law 34:472–8, 2006
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  2. ↵
    Colorado v. Connelly, 479 U.S. 157 (1986)
  3. ↵
    Appelbaum PS: A theory of ethics for forensic psychiatry. J Am Acad Psychiatry Law 25:233–47, 1997
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  4. ↵
    Simon RI, Wettstein RM: Toward the development of guidelines for the conduct of forensic psychiatric examinations. J Am Acad Psychiatry Law 25:17–30, 1997
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  5. ↵
    Candilis PJ: Reply to Schafer: ethics and the state extremism in defense of liberty. J Am Acad Psychiatry Law 29:452–6, 2001
    OpenUrlPubMed
  6. ↵
    AMA Code of Ethics: E.2.067 Torture, issued December 1997
  7. ↵
    Joint Resolution of the American Psychiatric Association and the American Psychological Association Against Torture, December 1985. Available at http://www.psych.org/edu/other_res/lib_archives/archives/198506.pdf. Accessed May 8, 2006
  8. ↵
    Zonana H: Torture and interrogations by psychiatrists. AAPL Newsletter. September, 2006, p 5
  9. ↵
    Hausman K: Assembly, board pass statement on detainee interrogations. Psychiatr News 41(12):1, 2006
  10. ↵
    American Psychiatric Association: The Principles of Medical Ethics With Annotations Especially Applicable to Psychiatry, 2006
  11. ↵
    Behnke S: Ethics and interrogations: comparing and contrasting the American Psychological, American Medical and American Psychiatric Association positions. Monitor Psychol 37(7):66, 2006
    OpenUrl
  12. ↵
    Clark PA: Medical ethics at Guantanamo Bay and Abu Ghraib: the problem of dual loyalty. J Law Med Ethics 34:570–80, 2006
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  13. ↵
    Allhoff F: Physician involvement in hostile interrogations. Cambridge Q Healthcare Ethics 15:392–402, 2006
    OpenUrlPubMed
PreviousNext
Back to top

In this issue

Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online: 34 (4)
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online
Vol. 34, Issue 4
December 2006
  • Table of Contents
  • Index by author
Print
Download PDF
Article Alerts
Sign In to Email Alerts with your Email Address
Email Article

Thank you for your interest in recommending The Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law site.

NOTE: We only request your email address so that the person you are recommending the page to knows that you wanted them to see it, and that it is not junk mail. We do not capture any email address.

Enter multiple addresses on separate lines or separate them with commas.
Commentary: It’s About the Fundamentals
(Your Name) has forwarded a page to you from Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law
(Your Name) thought you would like to see this page from the Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law web site.
CAPTCHA
This question is for testing whether or not you are a human visitor and to prevent automated spam submissions.
Citation Tools
Commentary: It’s About the Fundamentals
John L. Young
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online Dec 2006, 34 (4) 479-481;

Citation Manager Formats

  • BibTeX
  • Bookends
  • EasyBib
  • EndNote (tagged)
  • EndNote 8 (xml)
  • Medlars
  • Mendeley
  • Papers
  • RefWorks Tagged
  • Ref Manager
  • RIS
  • Zotero

Share
Commentary: It’s About the Fundamentals
John L. Young
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online Dec 2006, 34 (4) 479-481;
del.icio.us logo Twitter logo Facebook logo Mendeley logo
  • Tweet Widget
  • Facebook Like
  • Google Plus One

Jump to section

  • Article
    • Abstract
    • Current Views From Three Associations
    • Contrasting Philosophical Reflections
    • Conclusion
    • References
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF

Related Articles

Cited By...

More in this TOC Section

  • A Forensic Science-Based Model for Identifying and Mitigating Forensic Mental Health Expert Biases
  • Bias in Peer Review of Forensic Psychiatry Publications
  • Reconsidering the Relationship Between Criminal Insanity and Delusions
Show more Regular Article

Similar Articles

Site Navigation

  • Home
  • Current Issue
  • Ahead of Print
  • Archive
  • Information for Authors
  • About the Journal
  • Editorial Board
  • Feedback
  • Alerts

Other Resources

  • Academy Website
  • AAPL Meetings
  • AAPL Annual Review Course

Reviewers

  • Peer Reviewers

Other Publications

  • AAPL Practice Guidelines
  • AAPL Newsletter
  • AAPL Ethics Guidelines
  • AAPL Amicus Briefs
  • Landmark Cases

Customer Service

  • Cookie Policy
  • Reprints and Permissions
  • Order Physical Copy

Copyright © 2025 by The American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law