Skip to main content

Main menu

  • Home
  • Current Issue
  • Ahead of Print
  • Past Issues
  • Info for
    • Authors
    • Print Subscriptions
  • About
    • About the Journal
    • About the Academy
    • Editorial Board
  • Feedback
  • Alerts
  • AAPL

User menu

  • Alerts

Search

  • Advanced search
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law
  • AAPL
  • Alerts
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law

Advanced Search

  • Home
  • Current Issue
  • Ahead of Print
  • Past Issues
  • Info for
    • Authors
    • Print Subscriptions
  • About
    • About the Journal
    • About the Academy
    • Editorial Board
  • Feedback
  • Alerts
Book ReviewBooks and Media

Ethics of Total Confinement: A Critique of Madness, Citizenship, and Social Justice

Carl B. Greiner
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online June 2013, 41 (2) 316-317;
Carl B. Greiner
Omaha, NE
MD
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • Article
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF
Loading
By Bruce A. Arrigo, Heather Y. Bersot, Brian G. Sellers. New York: Oxford University Press, 2011. 300 pp. $75.00.

This book undertakes a vigorous challenge in reviewing the ethics structure of judicial approaches to juveniles charged as adults, solitary confinement of the mentally ill inmate, and sexually violent predators (SVPs). The authors are concerned about the rights of offenders and the perception that certain groups are not amenable to rehabilitation. Their premise is that the law ought to serve as a healing agent. The concepts are drawn from ethics, psychology, law, and social theory and require a substantial investment in a close reading of the text. This review focuses on the perspective on ethics in the text. Each approach to ethics has strengths and weaknesses, including virtue theory.

A review of contemporary ethics will assist in addressing the text. Utilitarian theory (Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill) attempts to balance good and negative effects; in medical training, this thinking is common in discussing informed consent and medication usage. A negative feature is the potential disregard for the needs of a minority group, such as prisoners. Duty-based ethics (Immanuel Kant) focuses on rules and includes universal principle such as not using others as a means rather than as an end; research that does not concern itself with the needs of the patient would be unethical. A negative feature is the expectation that a rule should be universal. If a prisoner has special needs, a Kantian approach could fail. Virtue ethics has a long, historical tradition (Plato and Aristotle) and emphasizes the virtues of character such as wisdom, courage, temperance, and justice. The goal of an ethical life is “human flourishing (a translation of the Greek term, eudaimonia)” (p 22). Attention to virtue ethics will assist one in taking moral action. The consequence of virtue is the improvement of social life. By extension, a vir-tue ethics approach to criminal justice emphasizes social reintegration and participation. The weak-ness of virtue ethics is its limitation in making specific decisions.

The authors review legal decisions regarding juveniles, solitary confinement, and sexually violent predators (SVPs); in each domain, the type of ethics-based justification is identified. Utilitarianism and duty-based approaches are the predominant sources of decision-making. By contrast, there was scant reference to virtue ethics in current decision-making. The authors starkly assert that a virtue-based approach would promote that “all individuals have value and as such can thrive ” (p 149). By encouraging the rehabilitation of the prisoners' lives, the authors contend that there can be an improved connection to the “large social world” and human flourishing.

The authors state that virtue ethics has strong similarities to psychological jurisprudence. Their vision encourages “judges as counselors.” The necessary reform would have attorneys, judges, and mental health workers become better educated in the practices of therapeutic jurisprudence and restorative justice which was identified as “mediated reconciliation” (p 7). An examination of the text assists the reader in determining if this approach is to be encouraged.

The analysis of the needs of the criminally charged and convicted is an essential corrective in maintaining a humane balance between societal protection and individual liberty. The authors identified a tendency to overstate or misidentify the level of recidivism in SVPs. The courts, having a faulty understanding of recidivism, are limited in their ability to craft meaningful approaches to SVPs.

Looking at the role of shame and humiliation in the lives of those convicted is an important investigation. In the development of registries for the SVPs, the authors note that the role of humiliation was designated as a “collateral consequence of a valid regulation” (p 132), and not as a direct effect; the court's distancing itself from the intended punitive aspect of humiliation is a troubling finding. One is reminded of the stocks used during American colonial times to publicly embarrass the offender. Highlighting the question of humiliation makes the reader concerned about the real-world functioning of SVP registries. A focus on virtue and character development suggests a different direction in producing shame and humiliation in the released SVP. To the extent that the SVP would be limited in social reintegration, the prior ethics (utilitarian or duty based) is deficient. Virtue ethics could support the character development of the convicted.

The authors describe the “debilitative effects” of solitary confinement on the mentally ill and a specific syndrome of negative psychological effects, termed special housing unit syndrome (p 67). The more serious consequences of solitary confinement include mental deterioration with increased anxiety, confusion, and hallucinations. Self-destructive behavior may actually be encouraged by the environment.

In the California case of Madrid v. Gomez1 (1995) the court states that inmates forfeit many rights and freedoms and that distress from segregation is not sufficient to invoke the Eighth Amendment. The authors express concern that this line of judicial thinking allows mentally ill inmates to be placed in solitary confinement where they may deteriorate further. The authors' unstated critical bridge is that a virtue ethic that focuses on the develop-ment of human character would result in a different decision.

The research in each of the major areas focuses on examining the ethics of the relevant case law. Identification of the ethics-based structure of statutes and judicial decision-making (duty based and consequentialism) is provided. However, the process of naming the ethics approach shortchanges a more in-depth analysis of how virtue ethics would necessarily provide a superior result. Further, there are general philosophical concerns about the value of virtue ethics in informing decisions about the correct thing to do. Virtue ethics is more connected with the development of a moral person than any specific decision that should be made. The shortcomings of virtue ethics in resolving complicated judicial questions are not in the text. Duty-based ethics focuses on treating individuals as the end rather than the means. The appropriate application of this theory would address many of the concerns about the treatment of prisoners.

The book is significant in reviewing case law and drawing renewed attention to the harsher realities of America's judicial system. Arguing for increased attention to prisoner rehabilitation and improving their ability to reintegrate into their communities is commendable. However, invoking virtue ethics will not resolve the thorny social, financial, and psychological problems of incarceration. The authors make a substantial leap from the importance of an individual's character to the promise of community integration and “human flourishing.”

Virtue ethics might provide improved social justice, but the approach is based on assertion rather than clear reasoning. The discernment of the variability and subgroupings of those who are convicted is not adequately covered. One of the core aspects of ethics analysis is to consider the alternatives. The specific prescription falls short and does not meet the problems addressed. The challenges of seriously antisocial prisoners and the problems of rehabilitation are not addressed. Specifically, important questions such as whether there are mentally ill patients for whom virtue ethics would not be an appropriate approach are not addressed. Despite these limitations, the book has valuable insights for patient readers.

Footnotes

  • Disclosures of financial or other potential conflicts of interest: None.

  • © 2013 American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law

Reference

  1. 1.↵
    Madrid v. Gomez, 889 F. Supp. 1146 (N.D. Cal. 1995).
PreviousNext
Back to top

In this issue

Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online: 41 (2)
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online
Vol. 41, Issue 2
1 Jun 2013
  • Table of Contents
  • Index by author
Print
Download PDF
Article Alerts
Sign In to Email Alerts with your Email Address
Email Article

Thank you for your interest in recommending The Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law site.

NOTE: We only request your email address so that the person you are recommending the page to knows that you wanted them to see it, and that it is not junk mail. We do not capture any email address.

Enter multiple addresses on separate lines or separate them with commas.
Ethics of Total Confinement: A Critique of Madness, Citizenship, and Social Justice
(Your Name) has forwarded a page to you from Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law
(Your Name) thought you would like to see this page from the Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law web site.
CAPTCHA
This question is for testing whether or not you are a human visitor and to prevent automated spam submissions.
Citation Tools
Ethics of Total Confinement: A Critique of Madness, Citizenship, and Social Justice
Carl B. Greiner
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online Jun 2013, 41 (2) 316-317;

Citation Manager Formats

  • BibTeX
  • Bookends
  • EasyBib
  • EndNote (tagged)
  • EndNote 8 (xml)
  • Medlars
  • Mendeley
  • Papers
  • RefWorks Tagged
  • Ref Manager
  • RIS
  • Zotero

Share
Ethics of Total Confinement: A Critique of Madness, Citizenship, and Social Justice
Carl B. Greiner
Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online Jun 2013, 41 (2) 316-317;
del.icio.us logo Twitter logo Facebook logo Mendeley logo
  • Tweet Widget
  • Facebook Like
  • Google Plus One

Jump to section

  • Article
    • Footnotes
    • Reference
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF

Related Articles

Cited By...

More in this TOC Section

  • Review of Anatomy of a Fall
  • A Forensic Review of Juror #2
  • Bright Young Women, Serial Killers, and the 1970s
Show more Books and Media

Similar Articles

Site Navigation

  • Home
  • Current Issue
  • Ahead of Print
  • Archive
  • Information for Authors
  • About the Journal
  • Editorial Board
  • Feedback
  • Alerts

Other Resources

  • Academy Website
  • AAPL Meetings
  • AAPL Annual Review Course

Reviewers

  • Peer Reviewers

Other Publications

  • AAPL Practice Guidelines
  • AAPL Newsletter
  • AAPL Ethics Guidelines
  • AAPL Amicus Briefs
  • Landmark Cases

Customer Service

  • Cookie Policy
  • Reprints and Permissions
  • Order Physical Copy

Copyright © 2025 by The American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law